AAUP's 1915 Declaration of Principles
The American Association of University Professors
President, John Dewey, Columbia University
And the AAUP Committee on Academic Freedom and Academic Tenure
Edwin R.A. Seligman (Economics), Columbia University, Chairman
Charles E. Bennett (Latin), Cornell University
James Q. Dealey (Political Science), Brown University
Richard T. Ely (Economics), University of Wisconsin
Henry W. Farnam (Political Science), Yale University
Frank A. Fetter (Economics), Princeton University
Franklin H. Giddings (Sociology), Columbia University
Charles A. Kofoid (Zoology), University of California
Arthur O. Lovejoy (Philosophy), The Johns Hopkins University
Frederick W. Padelford (English), University of Washington
Roscoe Pound (Law), Harvard University
Howard C. Warren (Psychology), Princeton University
Ulysses G. Weatherly (Sociology), Indiana University
Accepted this GENERAL DECLARATION OF PRINCIPLES on Dec 31st, 1915.
The term "academic freedom" has traditionally had two applications - to the freedom of the teacher
and to that of the student, Lehrfreiheit and Lernfreiheit. It need scarcely be pointed out that the
freedom which is the subject of this report is that of the teacher. Academic freedom in this sense
comprises three elements: freedom of inquiry and research; freedom of teaching within the
university or college; and freedom of extra-mural utterance and action. The first of these is
almost everywhere so safeguarded that the dangers of its infringement are slight. It may therefore
be disregarded in this report. The second and third phases of academic freedom are closely related,
and are often distinguished. The third, however, has an importance of its own, since of late it has
perhaps more frequently been the occasion of difficulties and controversies than has the question
of freedom of intra-academic teaching. All five of the cases which have recently been investigated
by committees of this Association have involved, at least as one factor, the right of university
teachers to express their opinions freely outside the university or to engage in political
activities in their capacity as citizens. The general principles which have to do with freedom of
teaching in both these senses seem to the committee to be in great part, though not wholly, the
same. In this report, therefore, we shall consider the matter primarily with reference to freedom
of teaching within the university, and shall assume that what is said thereon is also applicable to
the freedom of speech of university teachers outside their institutions, subject to certain
qualifications and supplementary considerations which will be pointed out in the course of the
report.
An adequate discussion of academic freedom must necessarily consider three matters:
(1) the scope and basis of the power exercised by those bodies having ultimate legal authority in
academic affairs;
(2) the nature of the academic calling;
(3) the function of the academic institution or university.
Basis of Academic Authority
American institutions of learning are usually controlled by boards of trustees as the ultimate
repositories of power. Upon them finally it devolves to determine the measure of academic freedom
which is to be realized in the several institutions. It therefore becomes necessary to inquire into
the nature of the trust reposed in these boards, and to ascertain to whom the trustees are to be
considered accountable.
The simplest case is that of the proprietary school or college designed for the propagation of
specific doctrines prescribed by those who have furnished its endowment. It is evident that in such
cases the trustees are bound by the deed of gift, and, whatever be their own views, are obligated
to carry out the terms of the trust. If a church or religious denomination established a college to
be governed by a board of trustees, with the express understanding that the college will be used as
an instrument of propaganda in the interests of the religious faith professed by the church or
denomination creating it, the trustees have a right to demand that everything be subordinated to
that end. If, again, as has happened in this country, a wealthy manufacturer establishes a special
school in a university in order to teach, among other things, the advantages of a protective
tariff, or if, as is also the case, an institution has been endowed for the purpose of propagating
the doctrines of socialism, the situation is analogous. All of these are essentially proprietary
institutions, in the moral sense. They do not, at least as regards one particular subject, accept
the principles of freedom of inquiry, of opinion, and of teaching; and their purpose is not to
advance knowledge by the unrestricted research and unfettered discussion of impartial
investigators, but rather to subsidize the promotion of the opinions held by the persons, usually
not of the scholar's calling, who provide the funds for their maintenance.
Concerning the desirability of the existence of such institutions, the committee does not desire
to express any opinion. But it is manifestly important that they should not be permitted to sail
under false colors. Genuine boldness and thoroughness of inquiry, and freedom of speech, are
scarcely reconcilable with the prescribed inculcation of a particular opinion upon a controverted
question.
Such institutions are rare, however, and are becoming ever more rare. We still have, indeed,
colleges under denominational auspices; but very few of them impose upon their trustees
responsibility for the spread of specific doctrines. They are more and more coming to occupy, with
respect to the freedom enjoyed by the members of their teaching bodies, the position of untrammeled
institutions of learning, and are differentiated only by the natural influence of their respective
historic antecedents and traditions.
Leaving aside, then, the small number of institutions of the proprietary type, what is the nature
of the trust reposed in the governing boards of the ordinary institutions of learning? Can colleges
and universities that are not strictly bound by their founders to a propagandist duty ever be
included in the class of institutions that we have just described as being in a moral sense
proprietary? The answer is clear. If the former class of institutions constitute a private or
proprietary trust, the latter constitute a public trust. The trustees are trustees for the public.
In the case of our state universities this is self-evident. In the case of most of our privately
endowed institutions, the situation is really not different. They cannot be permitted to assume the
proprietary attitude and privilege, if they are appealing to the general public for support.
Trustees of such universities or colleges have no moral right to bind the reason or the conscience
of any professor. All claim to such right is waived by the appeal to the general public for
contributions and for moral support in the maintenance, not of a propaganda, but of a nonpartisan
institution of learning. It follows that any university which lays restrictions upon the
intellectual freedom of its professors proclaims itself a proprietary institution, and should be so
described whenever it makes a general appeal for funds; and the public should be advised that the
institution has no claim whatever to general support or regard.
This elementary distinction between a private and a public trust is not yet so universally accepted
as it should be in our American institutions. While in many universities and colleges the situation
has come to be entirely satisfactory, there are others in which the relation of trustees to
professors is apparently still conceived to be analogous to that of a private employer to his
employees; in which, therefore, trustees are not regarded as debarred by any moral restrictions,
beyond their own sense of expediency, from imposing their personal opinions upon the teaching of
the institutions, or even from employing the power of dismissal to gratify their private
antipathies or resentments. An eminent university president thus described the situation not many
years since:
In the institutions of higher education the board of trustees is the body on whose discretion, good
feeling, and experience the securing of academic freedom now depends. There are boards which
leave nothing to be desired in these respects; but there are also numerous bodies that have
everything to learn with regard to academic freedom. These barbarous boards exercise an
arbitrary power of dismissal. They exclude from the teachings of the university unpopular or
dangerous subjects. In some states they even treat professors' positions as common political
spoils; and all too frequently, both in state and endowed institutions, they fail to treat the
members of the teaching staff with that high consideration to which their functions entitle them.¹
It is, then, a prerequisite to a realization of the proper measure of academic freedom in American
institutions of learning, that all boards of trustees should understand - as many already do - the
full implications of the distinction between private proprietorship and a public trust.
The Nature of the Academic Calling
The above-mentioned conception of a university as an ordinary business venture, and of academic
teaching as a purely private employment, manifests also a radical failure to apprehend the nature
of the social function discharged by the professional scholar. While we should be reluctant to
believe that any large number of educated persons suffer from such a misapprehension, it seems
desirable at this time to restate clearly the chief reasons, lying in the nature of the university
teaching profession, why it is to the public interest that the professional office should be one
both of dignity and of independence.
If education is the cornerstone of the structure of society and if progress in scientific knowledge
is essential to civilization, few things can be more important than to enhance the dignity of the
scholar's profession, with a view of attracting into its ranks men of the highest ability, of sound
learning, and of strong and independent character. This is the more essential because the pecuniary
emoluments of the profession are not, and doubtless never will be, equal to those open to the more
successful members of other professions. It is not, in our opinion, desirable that men should be
drawn into this profession by the magnitude of the economic rewards which it offers; but it is for
this reason the more needful that men of high gifts and character should be drawn into it by the
assurance of an honorable and secure position, and of freedom to perform honestly and according to
their own consciences the distinctive and important function which the nature of the profession
lays upon them.
That function is to deal at first hand, after prolonged and specialized technical training, with
the sources of knowledge; and to impart the results of their own and of their fellow-specialists'
investigation and reflection, both to students and to the general public, without fear or favor.
The proper discharge of this function requires (among other things) that the university teacher
shall be exempt from any pecuniary motive or inducement to hold, or to express, any
conclusion which is not the genuine and uncolored product of his own study or that of fellow-
specialists. Indeed, the proper fulfillment of the work of the professoriate requires that our
universities shall be so free that no fair-minded person shall find any excuse for even a suspicion
that the utterances of university teachers are shaped or restricted by the judgment, not of
professional scholars, but of inexpert and possibly not wholly disinterested persons outside of
their ranks. The lay public is under no compulsion to accept or to act upon the opinions of the
scientific experts whom, though the universities, it employs. But it is highly needful, in the
interest of society at large, that what purport to be the conclusions of men trained for, and
dedicated to, the quest for truth, shall in fact be the conclusions of such men, and not echoes of
the opinions of the lay public, or of the individuals who endow or manage universities. To the
degree that professional scholars, in the formation and promulgation of their opinions, are, or by
the character of their tenure appear to be, subject to any motive other than their own scientific
conscience and a desire for the respect of their fellow-experts, to that degree the university
teaching profession is corrupted; its proper influence upon public opinion is diminished and
vitiated; and society at large fails to get from its scholars, in an unadulterated form, the
peculiar and necessary service which it is the office of the professional scholar to furnish.
These considerations make still more clear the nature of the relationship between university
trustees and members of university faculties. The latter are the appointees, but not in any proper
sense the employees, of the former. For, once appointed, the scholar has professional functions to
perform in which appointing authorities have neither competency nor moral right to intervene. The
responsibility of the university teacher is primarily to the public itself, and to the judgment of
his own profession; and while, with respect to certain external conditions of his vocation, he
accepts a responsibility to the authorities of the institution in which he serves, in the
essentials of his professional activity his duty is to the wider public to which the institution
itself is morally amenable. So far as the university teacher's independence of thought and
utterance is concerned - though not in other regards - the relationship of professor to trustees
may be compared to that between judges of the Federal courts and the Executive who appoints them.
University teachers should be understood to be, with respect to the conclusions reached and
expressed by them, no more subject to the control of the trustees than are judges subject to the
control of the President with respect to their decisions; while of course, for the same reason,
trustees are no more to be held responsible for, or to be presumed to agree with, the opinions or
utterances of professors than the President can be assumed to approve of all the legal reasonings
of the courts. A university is a great and indispensable organ of the higher life of a civilized
community, in the work of which the trustees hold an essential and highly honorable place, but in
which the faculties hold an independent place, with quite equal responsibilities - and in relation
to purely scientific and educational questions, the primary responsibility.
Misconception or obscurity in this matter had undoubtedly been a source of occasional difficulty in
the past, and even in several instances during the current year, however much, in the main, a long
tradition of kindly and courteous intercourse between trustees and members of university faculties
has kept the question in the background.
The Function of the Academic Institution
The importance of academic freedom is most clearly perceived in the light of the purposes for which
universities exist. These are three in number.
A. To promote inquiry and advance the sum of human knowledge.
B. To provide general instruction to the students.
C. To develop experts for various branches of the public service.
Let us consider each of these. In the earlier stages of a nation's intellectual development, the
chief concern of educational institutions is to train the growing generation and to diffuse the
already accepted knowledge. It is only slowly that there comes to be provided in the highest
institutions of learning the opportunity for the gradual wresting from nature of her intimate
secrets. The modern university is becoming more and more the home of scientific research. There are
three fields of human inquiry in which the race is only at the beginning: natural science, social
science, and philosophy and religion, dealing with the relations of man to our nature, to his
fellowmen, and to ultimate realities and values. In natural science all that we have learned but
serves to make us realize more deeply how much more remains to be discovered. In social science in
its largest sense, which is concerned with the relations of men in society and with the conditions
of social order and well-being, we have learned only an adumbration of the laws which govern these
vastly complex phenomena. Finally, in the spiritual life, and in the interpretation of the general
meaning and ends of human existence and its relation to the universe, we are still far from a
comprehension of the final truths, and from a universal agreement among all sincere and earnest
men. In all of these domains of knowledge, the first condition of progress is complete and
unlimited freedom to pursue inquiry and publish its results. Such freedom is the breath in the
nostrils of all scientific activity.
The second function - which for a long time was the only function - of the American college or
university is to provide instruction for students. It is scarcely open to question that freedom of
utterance is as important to the teacher as it is to the investigator. No can be a successful
teacher unless he enjoys the respect of his students, and their confidence in his intellectual
integrity. It is clear, however, that this confidence will be impaired if there is suspicion on the
part of the student that the teacher is not expressing himself fully or frankly, or that college
and university teachers in general are a repressed and intimidated class who dare not speak with
that candor and courage which youth always demands in those whom it is to esteem. The average
student is a discerning observer, who soon takes the measure of his instructor. It is not only the
character of the instruction but also the character of the instructor that counts; and if the
student has reason to believe that the instructor is not true to himself, the virtue of the
instruction as an educative force is incalculably diminished. There must be in the mind of the
teacher no mental reservation. He must give the student the best of what he has and what he is.
The third function of the modern university is to develop experts for the use of the community. If
there is one thing that distinguishes the more recent developments of democracy, it is the
recognition by legislators of the inherent complexities of economic, social and political life, and
the difficulty of solving problems of technical adjustment without technical knowledge. The
recognition of this fact has led to a continually greater demand for the aid of experts in these
subjects, to advise both legislators and administrators. The training of such experts has,
accordingly, in recent years, become an important part of work of the universities; and in almost
every one of our higher institutions of learning the professors of the economic, social, and
political sciences have been drafted to an increasing extent into more or less unofficial
participation in the public service. It is obvious that here again the scholar must be absolutely
free not only to pursue his investigations but to declare the results of his researches, no matter
where they may lead him or to what extent they may come into conflict with accepted opinion. To be
of use to the legislator or the administrator, he must enjoy their complete confidence in the
disinterestedness of his conclusions.
It is clear, then, that the university cannot perform its threefold function without accepting and
enforcing to the fullest extent the principle of academic freedom. The responsibility of the
university as a whole is to the community at large, and any restriction upon the freedom of the
instructor is bound to react injuriously upon the efficiency and the morale of the institution, and
therefore ultimately upon the interests of the community.
The attempted infringements of academic freedom at present are probably not only of less frequency
than, but of a different character from, those to be found in former times. In the early period of
university development in America the chief menace to academic freedom was ecclesiastical, and the
disciplines chiefly affected were philosophy and the natural sciences. In more recent times the
danger zone has been shifted to the political and social sciences—though we still aehv sporadic
examples of the former class of cases in some of our smaller institutions. But it is precisely in
these provinces of knowledge in which academic freedom is now most likely to be threatened, that
the need for it is at the same time most evident. No person of intelligence believes that all of
our political problems have been solved, or that the final stage of social evolution has been
reached. Grave issues in the adjustment of men's social and economic relations are certain to call
for settlement in the years that are to come; and for the right settlement of them mankind will
need all wisdom, all the good will, all the soberness of mind, and all the knowledge drawn from
experience, that it can command. Toward this settlement the university has potentially its own very
great contribution to make; for if the adjustment reached is to be a wise one, it must take due
account of economic science, and be guided by that breadth of historic vision which it should be
one of the functions of a university to cultivate. But if the universities are to render any such
service toward the right solution of the social problems of the future, it is the first essential
that the scholars who carry on the work of universities shall not be in a position of dependence
upon the favor of any social class or group, that the disinterestedness and impartiality of their
inquiries and their conclusions shall be, so far as is humanly possible, beyond the reach of
suspicion.
The special dangers to freedom of teaching in the domain of the social sciences are evidently two.
The one which is the more likely to affect the privately endowed colleges and universities is the
danger of restrictions upon the expression of opinions which point toward extensive social
innovations, or call in question the moral legitimacy or social expediency of economic conditions
or commercial practices in which large vested interests are involved. In the political, social, and
economic field almost every question, no matter how large and general it at first appears, is more
or less affected with private or class interests; and, as the governing body of a university is
naturally made up of men who through their standing and ability are personally interested in great
private enterprises, the points of possible conflict are numberless. When to this is added the
consideration that benefactors, as well as most of the parents who send their children to privately
endowed institutions, themselves belong to the more prosperous and therefore usually to the more
conservative classes, it is apparent that, so long as effectual safeguards for academic freedom are
not established, there is a real danger that pressure from vested interests may, sometimes
deliberately and sometimes unconsciously, sometimes openly and sometimes subtly and in obscure
ways, be brought to bear upon academic authorities.
On the other hand, in our state universities the danger may be the reverse. Where the university is
dependent for funds upon legislative favor, it has sometimes happened that the conduct of
institution has been affected by political considerations; and where there is a definite
governmental policy or a strong public feeling on economic, social, or political questions, the
menace to academic freedom may consist in the repression of opinions that in the particular
political situation are deemed ultra-conservative rather than ultra-radical. The essential point,
however, is not so much that the opinion is of one or another shade, as that differs from the views
entertained by authorities. The question resolves itself into one of departure from accepted
standards; whether the departure is in the one direction or the other is immaterial.
This brings us to the most serious difficulty of this problem; namely, the dangers connected with
the existence in a democracy of an overwhelming and concentrated public opinion. The tendency of
modern democracy is for men to think alike, to feel alike, and to speak alike. Any departure from
the conventional standards is apt to be regarded with suspicion. Public opinion is at once the
chief safeguard of a democracy, and the chief menace to the real liberty of an individual. It almost
seems as if the danger of despotism cannot be wholly averted under any form of government. In a
political autocracy there is no effective public opinion, and all are subject to tyranny of the ruler; in a
democracy there is political freedom, but there is likely to be a tyranny of public opinion.
An inviolable refuge from such tyranny should be found in the university. It should be an
intellectual experiment station, where new ideas may germinate and where their fruit, though still
distasteful to the community as a whole, may be allowed to ripen until finally, perchance, it may
become part of the accepted intellectual food of the nation or of the world. Not less is it a
distinctive duty of the university to be the conservator of all genuine elements of value in the
past thought and life of mankind which are not in the fashion of the moment. Though it need not be
the "home of beaten causes," the university is, indeed, likely always to exercise a certain form of
conservative influence. For by its nature it is committed to the principle that knowledge should
precede action, to the caution (by no means synonymous with intellectual timidity) which is an
essential part of the scientific method, to a sense of the complexity of social problems, to the
practice of taking long views into the future, and to a reasonable regard for the teachings of
experience. One of its most characteristic functions in a democratic society is to help make public
opinion more self-critical and more circumspect, to check the more hasty and unconsidered impulses
of popular feeling, to train the democracy to the habit of looking before and after. It is
precisely this function of the university which is most injured by any restriction upon academic
freedom; and it is precisely those who most value this aspect of the university's work who should
most earnestly protest against any such restriction. For the public may respect, and be influenced
by, the counsels of prudence and of moderation which are given by men of science, if it believes
those counsels to be the disinterested expression of the scientific temper and of unbiased inquiry.
It is little likely to respect or heed them if it has reason to believe that they are the
expression of the interests, or the timidities, of the limited portion of the community which is in
a position to endow institutions of learning, or is most likely to be represented upon their boards
of trustees. And a plausible reason for this belief is given the public so long as our universities
are not organized in such a way as to make impossible any exercise of pressure upon professorial
opinions and utterances by governing boards of laymen.
Since there are no rights without corresponding duties, the considerations heretofore set down with
respect to the freedom of the academic teacher entail certain correlative obligations. The claim to
freedom of teaching is made in the interest of integrity and of the progress of scientific inquiry;
it is, therefore, only those who carry on their work in the temper of the scientific inquirer who
may justly assert this claim. The liberty of the scholar within the university to set forth his
conclusions, be they what they may, is conditioned by their being conclusions gained by a scholar's
method and held in a scholar's spirit; that is to say, they must be the fruits of competent and
patient and sincere inquiry, and they should be set forth with dignity, courtesy, and temperateness
of language. The university teacher, in giving instructions upon controversial matters, while he
is under no obligation to hide his own opinion under a mountain of equivocal verbiage, should, if
he is fit for his position, be a person of a fair and judicial mind; he should, in dealing with
such subjects, set forth justly, without suppression or innuendo, the divergent opinions of other
investigators; he should cause his students to become familiar with the best published expressions
of the great historic types of doctrine upon the questions at issue; and he should, above all,
remember that his business is not to provide his students with ready-made conclusions, but to train
them to think for themselves, and to provide them access to those materials which they need if they
are to think intelligently.
It is, however, for reasons which have already been made evident, inadmissible that the power of
determining when departures from the requirements of the scientific spirit and method have
occurred, should be vested in bodies not composed of members of the academic profession.
Such bodies necessarily lack full competency to judge of those requirements; their intervention
can never be exempt from the suspicion that it is dictated by other motives than zeal for the
integrity of science; and it is, in any case, unsuitable to the dignity of a great profession that
the initial responsibility for the maintenance of its professional standards should not be in the
hands of its own members. It follows that university teachers must be prepared to assume this
responsibility for themselves. They have hitherto seldom had the opportunity, or perhaps the
disposition, to do so. The obligation will doubtless, therefore, seem to many an unwelcome and
burdensome one; and for its proper discharge members of the profession will perhaps need to
acquire, in a greater measure than they at present possess it, the capacity for impersonal judgment
in such cases, and for judicial severity when the occasion requires it. But the responsibility
cannot, in this committee's opinion, be rightfully evaded. If this profession should prove itself
unwilling to purge its ranks of the incompetent and the unworthy, or to prevent the freedom which
it claims in the name of science from being used as a shelter for inefficiency, for superficiality,
or for uncritical and intemperate partisanship, it is certain that the task will be performed by
others--by others who lack certain essential qualifications for performing it, and whose action is
sure to breed suspicions and recurrent controversies deeply injurious to the internal order and the
public standing of universities. Your committee has, therefore, in the appended "Practical
Proposals" attempted to suggest means by which judicial action by representatives of the
profession, with respect to the matters here referred to, may be secured.
There is one case in which the academic teacher is under an obligation to observe certain special
restraints - namely, the instruction of immature students. In many of our American colleges, and
especially in the first two years of the course, the student's character is not yet fully formed,
his mind is still relatively immature. In these circumstances it may reasonably be expected that
the instructor will present scientific truth with discretion, that he will introduce the student to
new conceptions gradually, with some consideration for the student's preconceptions and traditions,
and with due regard to character-building. The teacher ought also to be especially on his guard
against taking unfair advantage of the students' immaturity by indoctrinating him with the
teacher's own opinions before the student has had an opportunity fairly to examine other opinions
upon the matters of question, and before he has sufficient knowledge and ripeness in judgment to be
entitled to form any definitive opinion of his own. It is not the least service which a college or
university may render to those under its instruction, to habituate them to looking not only
patiently but methodically on both sides, before adopting any conclusion upon controverted issues.
By these suggestions, however, it need scarcely be said that the committee does not intend to imply
that it is not the duty of an academic instructor to give to any students old enough to be in
college a genuine intellectual awakening and to arouse in them a keen desire to reach personally
verified conclusions upon all questions of general concernment to mankind, or of special
significance for their own time. There is much truth in some remarks recently made in this
connection by a college president:
Certain professors have been refused re-election lately, apparently because they set their students
to thinking in ways objectionable to the trustees. It would be well if more teachers were dismissed
because they fail to stimulate thinking of any kind. We can afford to forgive a college professor
what we regard as the occasional error of his doctrine, especially as we may be wrong, provided he
is a contagious center of intellectual enthusiasm. It is better for students to think about
heresies than not to think at all; better for them to climb new trails, and stumble over error if
need be, than to ride forever in upholstered ease in the overcrowded highway. It is a primary duty
of a teacher to make a student take an honest account of his stock of ideas, throw out the dead
matter, place revised price marks on what is left, and try to fill his empty shelves with new
goods.²
It is, however, possible and necessary that such intellectual awakening be brought about with
patience, considerateness, and pedagogical wisdom. There is one further consideration with regard to
the classroom utterances of college and university teachers to which the committee thinks it important
to call the attention of members of the profession, and of administrative authorities. Such utterances
ought always to be considered privileged communications. Discussions in the classroom ought not to be
supposed to be utterances for the public at large. They are often designed to provoke opposition or
arouse debate. It has, unfortunately, sometimes happened in this country that sensational newspapers
have quoted and garbled such remarks. As a matter of common law, it is clear that the utterances of an
academic instructor are privileged, and may not be published, in whole or part, without his authorization.³
But our practice, unfortunately, still differs from that of foreign countries, and no effective
check has in this country been put upon such unauthorized and often misleading publication. It is
much to be desired that test cases should be made of any infractions of the rule.In their extramural
utterances, it is obvious that academic teachers are under a peculiar obligation to avoid hasty or
unverified or exaggerated statements, and to refrain from intemperate or sensational modes of
expression. But subject to these restraints, it is not, in this committee's opinion, desirable that scholars
should be debarred from giving expression to their judgments upon controversial questions, or that
their freedom of speech, outside the university, should be limited to questions falling within their own
specialties. It is clearly not proper that they should be prohibited from lending their active support to
organized movements which they believe to be in the public interest. And, speaking broadly, it may be
said in the words of a nonacademic body already once quoted in a publication of the Association, that
"it is neither possible nor desirable to deprive a college professor of the political rights vouchsafed to
every citizen."⁴
It is, however, a question deserving of consideration by members of the Association, and by
university officials, how far academic teachers, at least those dealing with political, economic,
and social subjects, should be prominent in the management of our great party organizations, or
should be candidates for state or national offices of a distinctly political character. It is
manifestly desirable that such teachers have minds untrammeled by party loyalties, unexcited by
party enthusiasms, and unbiased by personal political ambitions; and that universities should
remain uninvolved in party antagonisms. On the other hand, it is equally manifest that the material
available for the service of the State would be restricted in a highly undesirable way, if it were
understood that no member of the academic profession should ever be called upon to assume the
responsibilities of public office. This question may, in the committee's opinion, suitably be made
a topic for special discussion at some future meeting of this Association, in order that a
practical policy, which shall do justice to the two partially conflicting considerations that bear
upon the matter, may be agreed upon.
It is, it will be seen, in no sense the contention of this committee that academic freedom implies
that individual teachers should be exempt from all restraints as to the matter or manner of their
utterances, either within or without the university. Such restraints as are necessary should in
the main, our committee holds, be self-imposed, or enforced by the public opinion of the
profession. But there may, undoubtedly, arise occasional cases in which the aberrations of
individuals may require to be checked by definite disciplinary action. What this report chiefly
maintains is that such action cannot with safety be taken by bodies not composed of members of the
academic profession. Lay governing boards are competent to judge concerning charges of habitual
neglect of assigned duties, on the part of individual teachers, and concerning charges of grave
moral delinquency. But in matters of opinion, and of the utterance of opinion, such boards cannot
intervene without destroying, to the extent of their intervention, the essential nature of a
university - without converting it from a place dedicated to openness of mind, in which the
conclusions expressed are the tested conclusions of trained scholars, into a place barred against the
access of new light, and precommitted to the opinions or prejudices of men who have not been set apart
or expressly trained for the scholar's duties. It is, in short, not the absolute freedom of utterance of the
individual scholar, but the absolute freedom of thought, of inquiry, of discussion, and of teaching, of the
academic profession, that is asserted by this declaration of principles. It is conceivable that our
profession may prove unworthy of its high calling, and unfit to exercise the responsibilities that belong
to it. But it will scarcely be said as yet to have given evidence of such unfitness. And the existence of
this Association, as it seems to our committee, must be construed as a pledge, not only that the
profession will earnestly guard those liberties without which it cannot rightly render its distinctive and
indispensable service to society, but also that it will with equal earnestness seek to maintain such
standards of professional character, and of scientific integrity and competency, as shall make it a fit
instrument for that service.
________________ _________ __
1 From "Academic Freedom," an address delivered before the New York Chapter of the Phi Beta Kappa Society at Cornell University, May 29, 1907, by Charles William Eliot, President of Harvard University.
2 William T. Foster, President of Reed College, in The Nation, November 11, 1915.
3 The leading case is Abernathy vs. Hutchinson, 3 L.J., Ch. 209. In this case, where damages were awarded, the court held as follows: "That persons who are admitted as pupils or otherwise to hear these lectures, although they are orally delivered and the parties might go to the extent, if they were able to do so, of putting down the whole by means of shorthand, yet they can do that only for the purpose of their own information and could not publish, for profit, that which they had not obtained the right of selling."
4 Report of the Wisconsin State Board of Public Affairs, December 1914.
**************************************
Source: Appendix A of Academic Freedom and Tenure: A Handbook of the American Association of the American Association of University Professors,, Edited by Louis Joughin, University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin. 1967. pp.155 - 176.
0 comments:
Post a Comment